Books by Wolfe, Tom
-
Wolfe, Tom.
I Am Charlotte Simmons.
(Audiobook, Unabridged).
New York: Macmillan Audio, 2004.
ISBN 978-0-312-42444-2.
-
Thomas
Sowell has written, “Each new generation born is in
effect an invasion of civilization by little barbarians, who
must be civilized before it is too late”. Tom Wolfe's extensively
researched and pitch-perfect account of undergraduate life at an
élite U.S. college in the first decade of the twenty-first century
is a testament to what happens when the barbarians sneak into the
gates of the cloistered cities of academe, gain tenure, and then
turn the next generation of “little barbarians” loose
into a state of nature, to do what their hormones and whims tell
them to.
Our viewpoint into this alien world (which the children and grandchildren
of those likely to be reading this chronicle inhabit, if they're lucky
[?] enough to go to one of those élite institutions which
groom them for entry into the New [or, as it is coming to be called,
Ruling] Class at the cost of between a tenth and a quarter of a million
dollars, often front-end loaded as debt onto the lucky students just
emerging into those years otherwise best spent in accumulating capital
to buy a house, start a family, and make the key
early
year investments
in retirement and inheritance for their progeny) is Charlotte Simmons of
Sparta, North Carolina, a Presidential Scholar from the hill country who,
by sheer academic excellence, has won a full scholarship to Dupont
University, known not only for its academic prestige, but also its
formidable basketball team.
Before arriving at Dupont, Charlotte knew precisely who she was,
what she wanted, and where she was going. Within days after arriving,
she found herself in a bizarre mirror universe where everything she
valued (and which the university purported to embody) was mocked by
the behaviour of the students, professors, and administrators.
Her discoveries are our discoveries of this alien culture which is
producing those who will decide our fate in our old age. Worry!
Nobody remotely competes with Tom Wolfe when it
comes to imbibing an alien culture, mastering its jargon and
patois, and fleshing out the characters who inhabit it.
Wolfe's talents are in full ascendance here, and this is a masterpiece
of contemporary pedagogic anthropathology. We are doomed!
The audio programme is distributed in four files, running
31 hours and 16 minutes and includes a brief interview
with the author at the end.
An Audio CD edition is available,
as is a paperback print edition.
October 2010
- Wolfe, Tom.
The Kingdom of Speech.
New York: Little, Brown, 2016.
ISBN 978-0-316-40462-4.
-
In this short (192) page book, Tom Wolfe returns
to his roots in the “new journalism”, of which he was
a pioneer in the 1960s. Here the topic is the theory of evolution;
the challenge posed to it by human speech (because no obvious
precursor to speech occurs in other animals); attempts, from
Darwin to Noam Chomsky to explain this apparent discrepancy and
preserve the status of evolution as a “theory of everything”;
and the evidence collected by linguist and anthropologist
Daniel Everett
among the
Pirahã
people of the Amazon basin in Brazil, which appears to falsify
Chomsky's lifetime of work on the origin of human language and
the universality of its structure. A second theme is contrasting
theorists and intellectuals such as Darwin and Chomsky
with “flycatchers” such as
Alfred Russel
Wallace, Darwin's rival for priority in publishing the theory
of evolution, and Daniel Everett, who work in the field—often in
remote, unpleasant, and dangerous conditions—to collect
the data upon which the grand thinkers erect their castles of hypothesis.
Doubtless fearful of the reaction if he suggested the theory of
evolution applied to the origin of humans, in his 1859 book
On the Origin of Species, Darwin only tiptoed
close to the question two pages from the end, writing,
“In the distant future, I see open fields for far more
important researches. Psychology will be securely based on a new
foundation, that of the necessary acquirement of each mental
power and capacity of gradation. Light will be thrown on the
origin of man and his history.” He needn't have been
so cautious: he fooled nobody. The very first review, five
days before publication, asked, “If a monkey has become
a man—…?”, and the tempest was soon at
full force.
Darwin's critics, among them
Max Müller,
German-born professor of languages at Oxford, and Darwin's
rival Alfred Wallace, seized upon human
characteristics which had no obvious precursors in the animals
from which man was supposed to have descended: a hairless body,
the capacity for abstract thought, and, Müller's emphasis,
speech. As Müller said, “Language is our Rubicon, and
no brute will dare cross it.” How could Darwin's theory,
which claimed to describe evolution from existing characteristics
in ancestor species, explain completely novel properties which animals
lacked?
Darwin responded with his 1871 The Descent of Man, and Selection
in Relation to Sex, which explicitly argued that there were
precursors to these supposedly novel human characteristics among
animals, and that, for example, human speech was foreshadowed by the
mating songs of birds. Sexual selection was suggested as the
mechanism by which humans lost their hair, and the roots of a number
of human emotions and even religious devotion could be found in the
behaviour of dogs. Many found these arguments, presented without any
concrete evidence, unpersuasive. The question of the origin of
language had become so controversial and toxic that a year later, the
Philological Society of London announced it would no longer accept
papers on the subject.
With the rediscovery of
Gregor Mendel's
work on genetics and subsequent
research in the field, a mechanism which could explain Darwin's
evolution was in hand, and the theory became widely accepted,
with the few discrepancies set aside (as had the Philological
Society) as things we weren't yet ready to figure out.
In the years after World War II, the social sciences became
afflicted by a case of “physics envy”. The contribution
to the war effort by their colleagues in the hard sciences in
areas such as radar, atomic energy, and aeronautics had been
handsomely rewarded by prestige and funding, while the more
squishy sciences remained in a prewar languor along with the
departments of Latin, Medieval History, and Drama. Clearly, what
was needed was for these fields to adopt a theoretical approach
grounded in mathematics which had served so well for chemists,
physicists, engineers, and appeared to be working for the new
breed of economists.
It was into this environment that in the late 1950s a young
linguist named
Noam Chomsky
burst onto the scene. Over its century and a half of history,
much of the work of linguistics had been cataloguing and studying
the thousands of languages spoken by people around the world, much
as entomologists and botanists (or, in the pejorative term of
Darwin's age, flycatchers) travelled to distant lands to
discover the diversity of nature and try to make sense of
how it was all interrelated. In his 1957 book,
Syntactic Structures, Chomsky, then just twenty-eight
years old and working in the building at MIT where radar had been developed
during the war, said all of this tedious and messy field work
was unnecessary. Humans had evolved (note, “evolved”)
a “language organ”, an actual physical structure within
the brain—the “language acquisition device”—which
children used to learn and speak the language they heard from
their parents. All human languages shared a “universal
grammar”, on top of which all the details of specific
languages so carefully catalogued in the field were just fluff, like
the specific shape and colour of butterflies' wings. Chomsky
invented the “Martian linguist” which was to come to
feature in his lectures, who he claimed, arriving on Earth, would
quickly discover the unity underlying all human languages. No longer
need the linguist leave his air conditioned office. As
Wolfe writes in chapter 4, “Now, all
the new, Higher Things in a linguist's life were to be found
indoors, at a desk…looking at learned journals filled with
cramped type instead of at a bunch of hambone faces in a cloud
of gnats.”
Given the alternatives, most linguists opted for the office, and for
the prestige that a theory-based approach to their field conferred,
and by the 1960s, Chomsky's views had taken over linguistics, with
only a few dissenters, at whom Chomsky hurled thunderbolts from his
perch on academic Olympus. He transmuted into a general-purpose
intellectual, pronouncing on politics, economics, philosophy,
history, and whatever occupied his fancy, all with the confidence
and certainty he brought to linguistics. Those who dissented
he denounced as “frauds”, “liars”, or
“charlatans”, including B. F. Skinner, Alan Dershowitz,
Jacques Lacan, Elie Wiesel, Christopher Hitchens, and Jacques
Derrida. (Well, maybe I agree when it comes to Derrida and Lacan.)
In 2002, with two colleagues, he published a new theory
claiming that recursion—embedding one thought within
another—was a universal property of human language and
component of the universal grammar hard-wired into the brain.
Since 1977, Daniel Everett had been living with and studying the
Pirahã in Brazil, originally as a missionary and later as
an academic linguist trained and working in the Chomsky tradition.
He was the first person to successfully learn the Pirahã
language, and documented it in publications. In 2005 he published
a paper in which he concluded that the language, one of the
simplest ever described, contained no recursion whatsoever.
It also contained neither a past nor future tense, description of
relations beyond parents and siblings, gender, numbers, and many
additional aspects of other languages. But the absence of recursion
falsified Chomsky's theory, which pronounced it a fundamental
part of all human languages. Here was a field worker, a
flycatcher, braving not only gnats but anacondas, caimans,
and just about every tropical disease in the catalogue, knocking the
foundation from beneath the great man's fairy castle of theory.
Naturally, Chomsky and his acolytes responded with their
customary vituperation, (this time, the adjective of choice for
Everett was “charlatan”). Just as they were preparing
the academic paper which would drive a stake through this nonsense,
Everett published
Don't Sleep, There Are Snakes,
a combined account of his thirty years with the Pirahã
and an analysis of their language. The book became a popular hit and
won numerous awards. In 2012, Everett followed up with
Language: The Cultural Tool,
which rejects Chomsky's view of language as an innate and universal
human property in favour of the view that it is one among a
multitude of artifacts created by human societies as a tool, and
necessarily reflects the characteristics of those societies.
Chomsky now refuses to discuss Everett's work.
In the conclusion, Wolfe comes down on the side of Everett, and
argues that the solution to the mystery of how speech evolved is
that it didn't evolve at all. Speech is simply a tool which humans
used their big brains to invent to help them accomplish their
goals, just as they invented bows and arrows, canoes, and
microprocessors. It doesn't make any more sense to ask how
evolution produced speech than it does to suggest it produced
any of those other artifacts not made by animals. He further
suggests that the invention of speech proceeded from initial
use of sounds as mnemonics for objects and concepts, then
progressed to more complex grammatical structure, but I found
little evidence in his argument to back the supposition, nor is
this a necessary part of viewing speech as an invented artifact.
Chomsky's grand theory, like most theories made up without grounding
in empirical evidence, is failing both by being falsified on its
fundamentals by the work of Everett and others, and also by the
failure, despite half a century of progress in neurophysiology,
to identify the “language organ” upon which it is
based.
It's somewhat amusing to see soft science academics rush to Chomsky's
defence, when he's arguing that language is biologically determined
as opposed to being, as Everett contends, a social construct whose
details depend upon the cultural context which created it. A hunter-gatherer
society such as the Pirahã living in an environment where food is
abundant and little changes over time scales from days to
generations, doesn't need a language as complicated as those living in
an agricultural society with division of labour, and it shouldn't be a
surprise to find their language is more rudimentary. Chomsky assumed
that all human languages were universal (able to express any concept),
in the sense
David Deutsch
defined universality in
The Beginning of Infinity, but why should
every people have a universal language when some cultures get along
just fine without universal number systems or alphabets? Doesn't
it make a lot more sense to conclude that people settle on a language,
like any other tools, which gets the job done? Wolfe then argues that
the capacity of speech is the defining characteristic of human
beings, and enables all of the other human capabilities and
accomplishments which animals lack. I'd consider this not proved. Why
isn't the definitive human characteristic the ability to make tools,
and language simply one among a multitude of tools humans have invented?
This book strikes me as one or two interesting blog posts
struggling to escape from a snarknado of Wolfe's 1960s style
verbal fireworks, including Bango!, riiippp,
OOOF!, and “a regular crotch crusher!”.
At age 85, he's still got it, but I wonder whether he, or his
editor, questioned whether this style of journalism is as
effective when discussing evolutionary biology and linguistics
as in mocking sixties radicals, hippies, or pretentious
artists and architects. There is some odd typography, as well.
Grave accents are used in words like “learnèd”,
presumably to indicate it's to be pronounced as two syllables,
but then occasionally we get an acute accent instead—what's
that supposed to mean? Chapter endnotes are given as
superscript letters while source citations are superscript numbers,
neither of which are easy to select on a touch-screen
Kindle edition. There is no index.
January 2017