Books by Smolin, Lee
- Smolin, Lee.
Einstein's Unfinished Revolution.
New York: Penguin Press, 2019.
ISBN 978-1-59420-619-1.
-
In the closing years of the nineteenth century, one of those
nagging little discrepancies vexing physicists was the behaviour
of the
photoelectric
effect. Originally discovered in 1887, the phenomenon causes
certain metals, when illuminated by light, to absorb the light
and emit electrons. The perplexing point was that there was a
minimum wavelength (colour of light) necessary for electron
emission, and for longer wavelengths, no electrons would be
emitted at all, regardless of the intensity of the beam of light.
For example, a certain metal might emit electrons
when illuminated by green, blue, violet, and ultraviolet light, with
the intensity of electron emission proportional to the light
intensity, but red or yellow light, regardless of how intense,
would not result in a single electron being emitted.
This didn't make any sense. According to
Maxwell's
wave theory of light, which was almost universally
accepted and had passed stringent experimental tests, the
energy of light depended upon the amplitude of the wave
(its intensity), not the wavelength (or, reciprocally,
its frequency). And yet the photoelectric effect didn't
behave that way—it appeared that whatever was causing the
electrons to be emitted depended on the wavelength
of the light, and what's more, there was a sharp cut-off
below which no electrons would be emitted at all.
In 1905, in one of his
“miracle
year” papers,
“On a Heuristic Viewpoint Concerning the Production and
Transformation of Light”, Albert Einstein suggested a
solution to the puzzle. He argued that light did not propagate
as a wave at all, but rather in discrete particles, or “quanta”,
later named “photons”, whose energy was proportional
to the wavelength of the light. This neatly explained the
behaviour of the photoelectric effect. Light with a wavelength
longer than the cut-off point was transmitted by photons whose
energy was too low to knock electrons out of metal they
illuminated, while those above the threshold could liberate
electrons. The intensity of the light was a measure of the
number of photons in the beam, unrelated to the
energy of the individual photons.
This paper became one of the cornerstones of the revolutionary
theory of
quantum
mechanics, the complete working out of which occupied much
of the twentieth century. Quantum mechanics underlies the
standard model
of particle physics, which is arguably the most thoroughly tested
theory in the history of physics, with no experiment showing
results which contradict its predictions since it was formulated
in the 1970s. Quantum mechanics is necessary to explain the
operation of the electronic and optoelectronic devices upon
which our modern computing and communication infrastructure
is built, and describes every aspect of physical
chemistry.
But quantum mechanics is weird. Consider: if light
consists of little particles, like bullets, then why
when you shine a beam of light on a
barrier
with two slits do you get an interference pattern with bright
and dark bands precisely as you get with, say, water waves?
And if you send a single photon at a time and try to measure
which slit it went through, you find it always went through one
or the other, but then the interference pattern goes away.
It seems like whether the photon behaves as a wave or a particle
depends upon how you look at it. If you have an hour, here is
grand master explainer
Richard Feynman
(who won his own Nobel Prize in 1965 for reconciling the
quantum mechanical theory of light and the electron with
Einstein's
special
relativity) exploring how profoundly weird the
double slit
experiment is.
Fundamentally, quantum mechanics seems to violate the principle
of realism, which the author defines as follows.
The belief that there is an objective physical world whose
properties are independent of what human beings know or
which experiments we choose to do. Realists also believe
that there is no obstacle in principle to our obtaining
complete knowledge of this world.
This has been part of the scientific worldview since antiquity
and yet quantum mechanics, confirmed by innumerable experiments,
appears to indicate we must abandon it. Quantum mechanics says
that what you observe depends on what you choose to measure; that
there is an absolute limit upon the precision with which you
can measure pairs of properties (for example position and momentum)
set by the
uncertainty
principle;
that it isn't possible to predict the outcome of experiments
but only the probability among a variety of outcomes;
and that particles which are widely separated
in space and time but which have interacted in the past are
entangled
and display correlations which no classical mechanistic theory
can explain—Einstein called the latter “spooky
action at a distance”. Once again, all of these effects
have been confirmed by precision experiments and are not
fairy castles erected by theorists.
From the formulation of the modern quantum theory in the 1920s,
often called the
Copenhagen
interpretation after the location of the institute where
one of its architects,
Neils Bohr,
worked, a number of eminent
physicists including Einstein and
Louis de Broglie
were deeply
disturbed by its apparent jettisoning of the principle of realism
in favour of what they considered a quasi-mystical view in which
the act of “measurement” (whatever that means) caused
a physical change
(wave
function collapse) in the state of a system. This seemed to
imply that the photon, or electron, or anything else, did not have
a physical position until it interacted with something else: until
then it was just an immaterial wave function which filled all of
space and (when squared) gave the probability of finding it at
that location.
In 1927, de Broglie proposed a
pilot wave theory
as a realist alternative to the Copenhagen interpretation. In
the pilot wave theory there is a real particle, which has a
definite position and momentum at all times. It is guided in
its motion by a pilot wave which fills all of space and is
defined by the medium through which it propagates. We cannot predict
the exact outcome of measuring the particle because we cannot have
infinitely precise knowledge of its initial position and
momentum, but in principle these quantities exist and are
real. There is no “measurement problem” because
we always detect the particle, not the pilot wave which guides it.
In its original formulation, the pilot wave theory exactly reproduced
the predictions of the Copenhagen formulation, and hence was not a
competing theory but rather an alternative
interpretation
of the equations of quantum mechanics. Many physicists who preferred
to “shut up and calculate” considered interpretations a
pointless exercise in phil-oss-o-phy, but de Broglie and
Einstein placed great value on retaining the principle of realism
as a cornerstone of theoretical physics. Lee Smolin sketches an
alternative reality in which “all the bright, ambitious students
flocked to Paris in the 1930s to follow de Broglie, and wrote textbooks
on pilot wave theory, while Bohr became a footnote, disparaged for
the obscurity of his unnecessary philosophy”. But that wasn't
what happened: among those few physicists who pondered what the
equations meant about how the world really works, the Copenhagen
view remained dominant.
In the 1950s, independently,
David Bohm
invented a pilot wave theory which he developed into a complete
theory of nonrelativistic quantum mechanics. To this day, a
small community of “Bohmians” continue to explore
the implications of his theory, working on extending it to be
compatible with special relativity. From a philosophical
standpoint the de Broglie-Bohm theory is unsatisfying in that it
involves a pilot wave which guides a particle, but upon which
the particle does not act. This is an
“unmoved
mover”, which all of our experience of physics argues
does not exist. For example, Newton's third law of motion holds
that every action has an equal and opposite reaction, and in
Einstein's general relativity, spacetime tells mass-energy how to
move while mass-energy tells spacetime how to curve. It seems
odd that the pilot wave could be immune from influence of the
particle it guides. A few physicists, such as Jack Sarfatti, have
proposed “post-quantum” extensions to Bohm's theory
in which there is back-reaction from the particle on the
pilot wave, and argue that this phenomenon might be accessible to
experimental tests which would distinguish post-quantum phenomena
from the predictions of orthodox quantum mechanics. A few
non-physicist crackpots have suggested these phenomena might even
explain
flying saucers.
Moving on from pilot wave theory, the author explores other attempts
to create a realist interpretation of quantum mechanics:
objective
collapse of the wave function, as in the
Penrose
interpretation; the
many
worlds interpretation (which Smolin calls “magical
realism”); and
decoherence
of the wavefunction due to interaction with the environment. He
rejects all of them as unsatisfying, because they fail to address
glaring lacunæ in quantum theory which are apparent from its
very equations.
The twentieth century gave us two pillars of theoretical physics:
quantum mechanics and
general
relativity—Einstein's geometric theory of gravitation.
Both have been tested to great precision, but they are fundamentally
incompatible with one another. Quantum mechanics describes the very
small: elementary particles, atoms, and molecules. General relativity
describes the very large: stars, planets, galaxies, black holes, and
the universe as a whole. In the middle, where we live our lives,
neither much affects the things we observe, which is why their
predictions seem counter-intuitive to us. But when you try to put
the two theories together, to create a theory of
quantum gravity,
the pieces don't fit. Quantum mechanics assumes there is a
universal clock which ticks at the same rate everywhere in the
universe. But general relativity tells us this isn't so: a simple
experiment shows that a clock runs slower when it's in a
gravitational field. Quantum mechanics says that it isn't possible
to determine the position of a particle without its interacting with
another particle, but general relativity requires the knowledge of
precise positions of particles to determine how spacetime curves and
governs the trajectories of other particles. There are a multitude
of more gnarly and technical problems in what Stephen
Hawking called “consummating the fiery marriage between
quantum mechanics and general relativity”. In particular,
the equations of quantum mechanics are
linear,
which means you can add together two valid solutions and get
another valid solution, while general relativity is
nonlinear,
where trying to disentangle the relationships of parts of the
systems quickly goes pear-shaped and many of the mathematical
tools physicists use to understand systems (in particular,
perturbation
theory) blow up in their faces.
Ultimately, Smolin argues, giving up realism means abandoning what
science is all about: figuring out what is really going on.
The incompatibility of quantum mechanics and general relativity
provides clues that there may be a deeper theory to which
both are approximations that work in certain domains (just as
Newtonian mechanics is an approximation of special relativity
which works when velocities are much less than the speed of
light). Many people have tried and failed to “quantise
general relativity”. Smolin suggests the problem is that
quantum theory itself is incomplete: there is a deeper
theory, a realistic one, to which our existing theory is
only an approximation which works in the present universe where
spacetime is nearly flat. He suggests that candidate theories
must contain a number of fundamental principles. They must be
background
independent, like general relativity, and discard such concepts
as fixed space and a universal clock, making both dynamic and
defined based upon the components of a system. Everything must
be relational: there is no absolute space or time; everything is defined
in relation to something else. Everything must have a cause, and
there must be a chain of causation for every event which traces
back to its causes; these causes flow only in one direction. There is
reciprocity: any object which acts upon another object is acted upon
by that object. Finally, there is the “identity of indescernibles”:
two objects which have exactly the same properties are the same
object (this is a little tricky, but the idea is that if you
cannot in some way distinguish two objects [for example, by their
having different causes in their history], then they are the same
object).
This argues that what we perceive, at the human scale and even in
our particle physics experiments, as space and time are actually
emergent properties of something deeper which was manifest in
the early universe and in extreme conditions such as gravitational
collapse to black holes, but hidden in the bland conditions which
permit us to exist. Further, what we believe to be “laws”
and “constants” may simply be precedents established by
the universe as it tries to figure out how to handle novel
circumstances. Just as complex systems like markets and evolution
in ecosystems have rules that change based upon events within
them, maybe the universe is “making it up as it goes along”,
and in the early universe, far from today's near-equilibrium, wild
and crazy things happened which may explain some of the puzzling
properties of the universe we observe today.
This needn't forever remain in the realm of speculation. It is
easy, for example, to synthesise a protein which has never existed
before in the universe (it's an example of a
combinatorial
explosion). You might try, for example, to crystallise this novel
protein and see how difficult it is, then try again later and see if
the universe has learned how to do it. To be extra careful, do it first
on the International Space Station and then in a lab on the Earth.
I suggested this almost twenty years ago as a test of
Rupert
Sheldrake's theory of morphic resonance, but (although
doubtless Smolin would shun me for associating his theory
with that one), it might produce interesting results.
The book concludes with a very personal look at the challenges
facing a working scientist who has concluded the paradigm
accepted by the overwhelming majority of his or her peers is
incomplete and cannot be remedied by incremental changes based
upon the existing foundation. He notes:
There is no more reasonable bet than that our current
knowledge is incomplete. In every era of the past our
knowledge was incomplete; why should our period be any
different? Certainly the puzzles we face are at least
as formidable as any in the past. But almost nobody bets
this way. This puzzles me.
Well, it doesn't puzzle me. Ever since I learned classical
economics, I've always learned to look at the incentives in
a system. When you regard academia today, there is huge risk
and little reward to get out a new notebook, look at the
first blank page, and strike out in an entirely new direction.
Maybe if you were a twenty-something patent examiner in a small city
in Switzerland in 1905 with no academic career or reputation at
risk you might go back to first principles and overturn space, time,
and the wave theory of light all in one year, but today's
institutional structure makes it almost impossible for a
young researcher (and revolutionary ideas usually come from
the young) to strike out in a new direction. It is a blessing
that we have deep thinkers such as Lee Smolin setting aside the
easy path to retirement to ask these deep questions today.
Here is a
lecture by
the author at the Perimeter Institute about the topics
discussed in the book. He concentrates mostly on the problems
with quantum theory and not the speculative solutions discussed
in the latter part of the book.
May 2019
- Unger, Roberto Mangabeira and Lee Smolin.
The Singular Universe and the Reality of Time.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
ISBN 978-1-107-07406-4.
-
In his 2013 book Time Reborn
(June 2013), Lee Smolin argued that, despite its extraordinary
effectiveness in understanding the behaviour of isolated systems, what
he calls the “Newtonian paradigm” is inadequate to
discuss cosmology: the history and evolution of the universe as a
whole. In this book, Smolin and philosopher Roberto Mangabeira Unger
expand upon that observation and present the case that the current
crisis in cosmology, with its appeal to multiple universes and
mathematical structures which are unobservable, even in principle, is
a consequence of the philosophical, scientific, and mathematical tools
we've been employing since the dawn of science attempting to be used
outside their domain of applicability, and that we must think
differently when speaking of the universe as a whole, which contains
all of its own causes and obeys no laws outside itself. The authors
do not present their own theories to replace those of present-day
cosmology (although they discuss the merits of several proposals), but
rather describe their work as a “proposal in natural
philosophy” which might guide investigators searching for those
new theories.
In brief, the Newtonian paradigm is that the evolution of physical
systems is described by differential equations which, given a set of
initial conditions, permit calculating the evolution of a system
in the future. Since the laws of physics at the microscopic
level are reversible, given complete knowledge of the state of a system
at a given time, its past can equally be determined. Quantum
mechanics modifies this only in that rather than calculating the
position and momentum of particles (or other observables), we
calculate the deterministic evolution of the wave function which
gives the probability of observing them in specific states in the future.
This paradigm divides physics into two components: laws (differential
equations) and initial conditions (specification of the initial state
of the system being observed). The laws themselves, although they
allow calculating the evolution of the system in time, are themselves
timeless: they do not change and are unaffected by the interaction of
objects. But if the laws are timeless and not subject to back-reaction
by the objects whose interaction they govern, where did they come
from and where do they exist? While conceding that
these aren't matters which working scientists spend much time
thinking about, in the context of cosmology they post serious
philosophical problems. If the universe all that is and contains
all of its own causes, there is no place for laws which are outside
the universe, cannot be acted upon by objects within it, and have
no apparent cause.
Further, because mathematics has been so effective in expressing the
laws of physics we've deduced from experiments and observations,
many scientists have come to believe that mathematics can be a
guide to exploring physics and cosmology: that some mathematical
objects we have explored are, in a sense, homologous to the universe,
and that learning more about the mathematics can be a guide to
discoveries about reality.
One of the most fundamental discoveries in cosmology, which has
happened within the lifetimes of many readers of this book,
including me, is that the universe has a history. When
I was a child, some scientists (a majority, as I recall) believed
the universe was infinite and eternal, and that observers at any
time in the past or future would observe, at the largest scales,
pretty much the same thing. Others argued for an origin at a finite
time in the past, with the early universe having a temperature
and density much greater than at present—this theory was
mocked as the “big bang”. Discovery of the cosmic
background radiation and objects in the distant universe which
did not at all resemble those we see nearby decisively decided
this dispute in favour of the big bang, and recent precision
measurements have allowed determination of when it happened and
how the universe evolved subsequently.
If the universe has a finite age, this makes the idea of
timeless laws even more difficult to accept. If the universe is
eternal, one can accept that the laws we observe have always been
that way and always will be. But if the universe had an origin we
can observe, how did the laws get baked into the universe? What
happened before the origin we observe? If every event has a cause,
what was the cause of the big bang?
The authors argue that in cosmology—a theory encompassing
the entire universe—a global privileged time must govern
all events. Time flows not from some absolute clock as envisioned
by Newtonian physics or the elastic time of special and general
relativity, but from causality: every event has one or more causes,
and these causes are unique. Depending upon their position and state
of motion, observers will disagree about the durations measured
by their own clocks, and on the order in which things
at different positions in space occurred (the relativity of
simultaneity), but they will always observe a given event to have the
same cause(s), which precede it. This relational notion of time,
they argue, is primordial, and space may be emergent from it.
Given this absolute and privileged notion of time (which many
physicists would dispute, although the authors argue does not
conflict with relativity), that time is defined by the
causality of events which cause change in the universe, and that
there is a single universe with nothing outside it and which contains all
of its own causes, then is it not plausible to conclude that the
“laws” of physics which we observe are not timeless
laws somehow outside the universe or grounded in a Platonic mathematics
beyond the universe, but rather have their own causes, within the
universe, and are subject to change: just as there is no “unmoved
mover”, there is no timeless law? The authors, particularly
Smolin, suggest that just as we infer laws from observing
regularities in the behaviour of systems within the universe
when performing experiments in various circumstances, these laws
emerge as the universe develops “habits” as interactions
happen over and over. In the present cooled-down state of the
universe, it's very much set in its ways, and since everything has
happened innumerable times we observe the laws to be unchanging. But
closer to the big bang or at extreme events in the subsequent universe,
those habits haven't been established and true novelty can occur.
(Indeed, simply by synthesising a protein with a hundred amino acids
at random, you're almost certain to have created a molecule which has
never existed before in the observable universe, and it may be harder
to crystallise the first time than subsequently. This appears to
be the case. This is my observation, not the authors'.)
Further, not only may the laws change, but entirely new kinds of
change may occur: change itself can change. For example, on
Earth, change was initially governed entirely by the laws
of physics and chemistry (with chemistry ultimately based upon
physics). But with the emergence of life, change began to be
driven by evolution which, while at the molecular level was
ultimately based upon chemistry, created structures which
equilibrium chemistry never could, and dramatically changed the
physical environment of the planet. This was not just change, but
a novel kind of change. If it happened here, in our own recent
(in cosmological time) history, why should we assume other novel
kinds of change did not emerge in the early universe, or will not
continue to manifest themselves in the future?
This is a very difficult and somewhat odd book. It is written in two
parts, each by one of the co-authors, largely independent of one another.
There is a twenty page appendix in which the authors discuss their
disagreements with one another, some of which are fundamental.
I found Unger's part tedious, repetitive, and embodying all of things
I dislike about academic philosophers. He has some important things
to say, but I found that slogging through almost 350 pages of it was
like watching somebody beat a moose to death with an aluminium
baseball bat: I believe a good editor, or even a mediocre one, could
have cut this to 50 pages without losing anything and making the
argument more clearly than trying to dig it out of this blizzard
of words. Lee Smolin is one of the most lucid communicators among
present-day research scientists, and his part is clear, well-argued,
and a delight to read; it's just that you have to slog through the
swamp to get there.
While suggesting we may have been thinking about cosmology all wrong,
this is not a book which suggests either an immediate theoretical or
experimental programme to explore these new ideas. Instead, it
intends to plant the seed that, apart from time and causality,
everything may be emergent, and that when we think about
the early universe we cannot rely upon the fixed framework of our
cooled-down universe with its regularities. Some of this is obvious
and non-controversial: before there were atoms, there was no periodic
table of the elements. But was there a time before there was
conservation of energy, or before locality?
September 2015
- Smolin, Lee.
Time Reborn.
New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2013.
ISBN 978-0-547-51172-6.
-
Early in his career, the author received some unorthodox career
advice from Richard Feynman. Feynman noted that in physics, as in
all sciences, there were a large number of things that most
professional scientists believed which nobody had been able to
prove or demonstrate experimentally. Feynman's insight was that,
when considering one of these problems as an area to investigate,
there were two ways to approach it. The first was to try to
do what everybody had failed previously to accomplish. This, he
said, was extremely difficult and unlikely to succeed, since it
assumes you're either smarter than everybody who has tried before
or have some unique insight which eluded them. The other path is
to assume that the failure of numerous brilliant people might
indicate that what they were trying to demonstrate was, in
fact, wrong, and that it might be wiser for the ambitious
scientist to search for evidence to the contrary.
Based upon the author's previous work and publications, I picked up
this book expecting a discussion of the
problem of time in quantum gravity.
What I found was something breathtakingly more ambitious. In essence,
the author argues that when it comes to cosmology: the physics of
the universe as a whole, physicists have been doing it wrong
for centuries, and that what he calls the “Newtonian
paradigm” must be replaced with one in which time
is fundamental in order to stop speaking nonsense.
The equations of
general relativity,
especially when formulated in attempts to create a quantum theory of
gravitation, seem to suggest that our perception of time is an
illusion: we live in a timeless
block universe,
in which our consciousness can be thought of as a cursor moving through
a fixed, deterministic spacetime. In general relativity, the rate of
perceived flow of time depends upon one's state of motion and the
amount of mass-energy in the vicinity of the observer, so it makes no
sense to talk about any kind of global time co-ordinate. Quantum
mechanics, on the other hand, assumes there is a global clock, external
to the system and unaffected by it, which governs the evolution of the
wave function. These views are completely incompatible—hence the
problem of time in quantum gravity.
But the author argues that “timelessness” has its roots much
deeper in the history and intellectual structure of physics. When one
uses Newtonian mechanics to write down a differential equation which
describes the path of a ball thrown upward, one is reducing a process
which would otherwise require enumerating a list of positions and times
to a timeless relationship which is valid over the entire trajectory.
Time appears in the equation simply as a label which causes it to
emit the position at that moment. The equation of motion, and, more
importantly, the laws of motion which allow us to write it down for
this particular case, are entirely timeless: they affect the object
but are not affected by it, and they appear to be specified outside the
system.
This, when you dare to step back and think about it, is distinctly
odd. Where did these laws come from? Well, in Newton's day
and in much of the history of science since, most scientists would say
they were prescribed by a benevolent Creator. (My own view that they
were put into the
simulation
by the 13 year old superkid who created it
in order to win the Science Fair with the most interesting result,
generating the maximum complexity, is isomorphic to this explanation.)
Now, when you're analysing a system “in a box”, it makes perfect
sense to assume the laws originate from outside and are fixed; after all, we can
compare experiments run in different boxes and convince ourselves that
the same laws obtain regardless of symmetries such as translation,
orientation, or boost. But note that once we try to generalise this
to the entire universe, as we must in cosmology, we run into a philosophical
speed bump of singularity scale. Now we cannot escape the question
of where the laws came from. If they're from inside the universe, then
there must have been some dynamical process which created them. If they're
outside the universe, they must have had to be imposed by some process
which is external to the universe, which makes no sense if you define
the universe as all there is.
Smolin suggests that laws exist within our universe, and that they
evolve in an absolute time, which is primordial. There
is no
unmoved mover:
the evolution of the universe (and the possibility that universes
give birth to other universes) drives the evolution of the laws of
physics. Perhaps the
probabilistic results we observe
in quantum mechanical processes are not built-in ahead of time
and prescribed by timeless laws outside the universe, but rather a
random choice from the results of previous similar measurements.
This “principle of precedence”, which is remarkably similar
to that of English
common law,
perfectly reproduces the results of
most tests of quantum mechanics, but may be testable by precision
experiments where circumstances never before created in the universe
are measured, for example in quantum computing. (I am certain Prof.
Smolin would advocate for my being beheaded were I to point out the
similarity of this hypothesis with
Rupert Sheldrake's
concept of
morphic
resonance; some years ago I suggested to Dr Sheldrake a protein
crystallisation experiment on the International Space Station
to test this theory; it is real science, but
to this date nobody has done it. Few wish to risk their careers testing
what “everybody knows”.)
This is one those books you'll need to think about after you've read it,
then after some time, re-read to get the most out of it. A collection
of
online appendices
expand upon topics discussed in the book.
An hour-long video
discussion of the ideas in the book by the author and the
intellectual path which led him to them is available.
June 2013
- Smolin, Lee.
The Trouble with Physics.
New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2006.
ISBN 0-618-55105-0.
-
The first forty years of the twentieth century saw a
revolution in fundamental physics: special and general
relativity changed our perception of space, time, matter, energy, and
gravitation; quantum theory explained all of chemistry
while wiping away the clockwork determinism of
classical mechanics and replacing it with a deeply
mysterious theory which yields fantastically precise
predictions yet nobody really understands at its deepest
levels; and the structure of the atom was elucidated, along
with important clues to the mysteries of the nucleus. In
the large, the universe was found to be enormously larger
than expected and expanding—a dynamic arena which
some suspected might have an origin and a future vastly
different than its present state.
The next forty years worked out the structure and interactions
of the particles and forces which constitute matter and
govern its interactions, resulting in a standard model of
particle physics with precisely defined theories which predicted
all of the myriad phenomena observed in particle accelerators
and in the highest energy events in the heavens. The universe
was found to have originated in a big bang no more distant than
three times the age of the Earth, and the birth cry of the universe
had been detected by radio telescopes.
And then? Unexpected by almost all practitioners of high energy
particle physics, which had become an enterprise larger by far than
all of science at the start of the century, progress stopped. Since
the wrapping up of the standard model around 1975, experiments have
simply confirmed its predictions (with the exception of the discovery
of neutrino oscillations and consequent mass, but that can be
accommodated within the standard model without changing its
structure), and no theoretical prediction of phenomena beyond the
standard model has been confirmed experimentally.
What went wrong? Well, we certainly haven't reached the End of
Science or even the End of Physics, because the theories which govern
phenomena in the very small and very large—quantum mechanics and
general relativity—are fundamentally incompatible with one
another and produce nonsensical or infinite results when you attempt
to perform calculations in the domain—known to exist from
astronomical observations—where both must apply. Even a
calculation as seemingly straightforward as estimating the energy of
empty space yields a result which is 120 orders of magnitude
greater than experiment shows it to be: perhaps the most
embarrassing prediction in the history of science.
In the first chapter of this
tour de force, physicist
Lee Smolin poses “The Five Great Problems in
Theoretical Physics”, all of which are just as mysterious
today as they were thirty-five years ago. Subsequent chapters
explore the origin and nature of these problems, and
how it came to be, despite unprecedented
levels of funding for theoretical and experimental physics,
that we seem to be getting nowhere in resolving any of these
fundamental enigmas.
This prolonged dry spell in high energy physics has seen the emergence
of string theory (or superstring theory, or M-theory, or whatever
they're calling it this year) as the dominant research program in
fundamental physics. At the outset, there were a number of excellent
reasons to believe that string theory pointed the way
to a grand unification of all of the forces and particles of physics,
and might answer many, if not all, of the Great Problems. This
motivated many very bright people, including the author (who, although
most identified with loop quantum gravity research, has
published in string theory as well) to pursue this direction. What is
difficult for an outsider to comprehend, however, is how a theoretical
program which, after thirty-five years of intensive effort, has yet to
make a single prediction testable by a plausible experiment; has
failed to predict any of the major scientific surprises that have
occurred over those years such as the accelerating expansion of the
universe and the apparent variation in the fine structure constant;
that does not even now exist in a well-defined mathematical form; and has
not been rigorously proved to be a finite theory; has established
itself as a virtual intellectual monopoly in the academy, forcing
aspiring young theorists to work in string theory if they are to have
any hope of finding a job, receiving grants, or obtaining tenure.
It is this phenomenon, not string theory itself, which, in the
author's opinion, is the real “Trouble with Physics”.
He considers string theory as quite possibly providing clues (though
not the complete solution) to the great problems, and finds much to
admire in many practitioners of this research. But monoculture is
as damaging in academia as in agriculture, and when it becomes deeply
entrenched in research institutions, squeezes out other approaches
of equal or greater merit. He draws the distinction between “craftspeople”,
who are good at performing calculations, filling in blanks, and extending
an existing framework, and “seers”, who make the great
intellectual leaps which create entirely new frameworks. After
thirty-five years with no testable result, there are plenty of reasons
to suspect a new framework is needed, yet our institutions select out
those most likely to discover them, or force them to spend their most
intellectually creative years doing tedious string theory calculations at the
behest of their elders.
In the final chapters, Smolin looks at how academic
science actually works today: how hiring and tenure decisions are
made, how grant applications are evaluated, and the difficult
career choices young physicists must make to work within this system.
When reading this, the word “Gosplan”
(Госпла́н)
kept flashing
through my mind, for the process he describes resembles nothing so
much as central planning in a command economy: a small group of
senior people, distant from the facts on the ground and the cutting
edge of intellectual progress, trying to direct a grand effort in
the interest of “efficiency”. But the lesson of more
than a century of failed socialist experiments is that, in the timeless words
of Rocket J. Squirrel, “that trick never works”—the
decisions inevitably come down on the side of risk aversion, and are
often influenced by cronyism and toadying to figures in authority.
The concept of managing risk and reward by building a diversified
portfolio of low and high risk placements which is second nature
to managers of venture capital funds and industrial research and
development laboratories appears to be totally absent in academic
science, which is supposed to be working on the most difficult and
fundamental questions. Central planning works abysmally for cement and
steel manufacturing; how likely is it to spark the next scientific
revolution?
There is much more to ponder: why string theory, as presently defined,
cannot possibly be a complete theory which subsumes general
relativity; hints from experiments which point to new physics beyond
string theory; stories of other mathematically beautiful theories
(such as SU(5) grand unification) which experiment showed to be dead
wrong; and a candid view of the troubling groupthink, appeal to
authority, and intellectual arrogance of some members of the string
theory community. As with all of Smolin's writing, this is a joy to
read, and you get the sense that he's telling you the straight story,
as honestly as he can, not trying to sell you something. If
you're interested in these issues, you'll probably also want to read
Leonard Susskind's pro-string
The Cosmic Landscape
(March 2006) and Peter Woit's sceptical
Not Even Wrong
(June 2006).
September 2006