Books by D'Souza, Dinesh
- D'Souza, Dinesh.
Life After Death: The Evidence.
Washington: Regnery Publishing, 2009
ISBN 978-1-59698-099-0.
-
Ever since the Enlightenment, and to an increasing extent today,
there is a curious disconnect between the intellectual élite
and the population at large. The overwhelming majority of human
beings who have ever lived believed in their survival, in one form
or another, after death, while materialists, reductionists, and
atheists argue that this is nothing but wishful thinking; that
there is no physical mechanism by which consciousness could survive
the dissolution of the neural substrate in which it is instantiated,
and point to the lack of any evidence for survival after death. And
yet a large majority of people alive today beg to differ. As atheist
H. G. Wells put it in a very different context, they sense that
“Worlds may freeze and suns may perish, but there stirs
something within us now that can never die again.” Who is
right?
In this slim (256 page) volume, the author examines the scientific,
philosophical, historical, and moral evidence for and implications of
survival after death. He explicitly excludes religious revelation
(except in the final chapter, where some evidence he cites as
historical may be deemed by others to be argument from scriptural
authority). Having largely excluded religion from the argument, he
explores the near-universality of belief in life after death across
religious traditions and notes the common threads uniting
them.
But traditions and beliefs do not in any way address the actual
question: does our individual consciousness, in some manner,
survive the death of our bodies? While materialists discard such
a notion as absurd, the author argues that there is nothing in our
present-day understanding of physics, evolutionary biology, or
neuroscience which excludes this possibility. In fact, the
complete failure so far to understand the physical basis of consciousness
can be taken as evidence that it may be a phenomenon independent of
its physical instantiation: structured information which could
conceivably transcend the hardware on which it currently operates.
Computer users think nothing these days of backing up their old
computer, loading the backups onto a new machine (which may use
a different processor and operating system), and with a little
upward compatibility magic, having everything work pretty much as
before. Do your applications and documents from the old computer
die when you turn it off for the last time? Are they reincarnated
when you load them into the replacement machine? Will they live
forever as long as you continue to transfer them to successive
machines, or on backup tapes? This may seem a silly analogy, but
consider that materialists consider your consciousness and self
to be nothing other than a pattern of information evolving in a
certain way according to the rules of neural computation. Do the
thought experiment: suppose nanotechnological robots replaced your
meat neurons one by one with mechanical analogues with the same
external electrochemical interface. Eventually your brain would
be entirely different physically, but would your consciousness change
at all? Why? If it's just a bunch of components, then replacing
protein components with silicon (or whatever) components which work
in the same way should make no difference at all, shouldn't it?
A large part of what living organisms do is sense their
external environment and interact with it. Unicellular
organisms swim along the gradient of increasing nutrient concentration.
Other than autonomic internal functions of which we are aware
only when they misbehave, humans largely experience the world
through our sensory organs, and through the internal sense of self which
is our consciousness. Is it not possible that the latter is much
like the former—something external to the meatware
of our body which is picked up by a sensory organ, in this case
the neural networks of the brain?
If this be the case, in the same sense that the external world
does not cease to exist when our eyes, ears, olfactory, and
tactile sensations fail at the time of death or due to injury,
is it not plausible that dissolution of the brain, which receives
and interacts with our external consciousness, need not mean the
end of that incorporeal being?
Now, this is pretty out-there stuff, which might cause the author
to run from the room in horror should he hear me expound it.
Fine: this humble book reviewer spent a substantial amount of
time contributing to a project seeking evidence for existence of
global, distributed
consciousness,
and has concluded that such has been
demonstrated to exist
by the standards accepted by most of the “hard” sciences.
But let's get back to the book itself.
One thing you won't find here is evidence based upon hauntings,
spiritualism, or other supposed contact with the dead (although
I must admit, Chicago election returns are
awfully persuasive as to the ability of the dead to intervene
in affairs of the living). The author does explore near death
experiences, noting their universality across very different
cultures and religious traditions, and evidence for reincarnation,
which he concludes is unpersuasive (but see the research of
Ian Stevenson
and decide for yourself). The exploration of a physical basis for the
existence of other worlds (for example, Heaven and Hell) cites the
“multiverse” paradigm, and invites sceptics of that
“theory of anything” to denounce it as “just as
plausible as life after death”—works for me.
Excuse me for taking off on a tangent here, but it is, in a
formal sense. If you believe in an infinite chaotically inflating
universe with random initial conditions, or in
Many Worlds in One (October 2006),
then Heaven and Hell explicitly exist, not only once in the
multiverse, but an infinity of times. For every moment in your
life that you may have to ceased to exist, there is a universe
somewhere out there, either elsewhere in the multiverse or in some
distant region far from our cosmic horizon in this universe, where there's
an observable universe identical to our own up to that instant which diverges
thence into one which grants you eternal reward or torment for your
actions. In an infinite universe with random initial conditions,
every possibility occurs an infinite number of times. Think about
it, or better yet, don't.
The chapter on morality is particularly challenging and enlightening.
Every human society has had a code of morality (different in the
details, but very much the same at the core), and most of these
societies have based their moral code upon a belief in cosmic
justice in an afterlife. It's self-evident that bad guys sometimes
win at the expense of good guys in this life, but belief that
the score will be settled in the long run has provided a powerful
incentive for mortals to conform to the norms which their societies
prescribe as good. (I've deliberately written the last sentence in
the post-modern idiom; I consider many moral norms absolutely good or bad
based on gigayears of evolutionary history, but I needn't introduce
that into evidence to prove my case, so I won't.) From an
evolutionary standpoint, morality is a survival trait of the family or
band: the hunter who shares the kill with his family and tribe will
have more descendants than the gluttonous loner. A tribe which
produces males who sacrifice themselves to defend their women and
children will produce more offspring than the tribe whose males
value only their own individual survival.
Morality, then, is, at the group level, a selective trait, and
consequently it's no surprise that it's universal among human
societies. But if, as serious atheists such as Bertrand Russell
(as opposed to the lower-grade atheists we get today) worried,
morality has been linked to religion and belief in an afterlife
in every single human society to date, then how is morality (a
survival characteristic) to be maintained in the absence of
these beliefs? And if evolution has selected us to believe in
the afterlife for the behavioural advantages that belief confers in
the here and now, then how successful will the atheists be in
extinguishing a belief which has conferred a behavioural selective
advantage upon thousands of generations of our ancestors? And
how will societies which jettison such belief fare in competition
with those which keep it alive?
I could write much more about this book, but then you'd have to read a
review even longer than the book, so I'll spare you. If you're
interested in this topic (as you'll probably eventually be as you get
closer to the checkered flag), this is an excellent introduction, and
the end notes provide a wealth of suggestions for additional reading.
I doubt this book will shake the convictions of either the confirmed
believers or the stalwart sceptics, but it will
provide much for both to think about, and perhaps motivate some folks
whose approach is “I'll deal with that when the time
comes” (which has been pretty much my own) to consider the
consequences of what may come next.
February 2010
- D'Souza, Dinesh.
What's So Great About Christianity.
Washington: Regnery Publishing, 2007.
ISBN 978-1-59698-517-9.
-
I would almost certainly never have picked up a book with this
title had I not happened to listen to a
podcast
interview with the author last October. In it, he says that
his goal in writing the book was to engage the contemporary
intellectually militant atheists such as
Richard Dawkins,
Sam Harris,
Christopher Hitchens,
Daniel Dennett, and
Victor Stenger
on their own turf, mounting a rational argument
in favour of faith in general and Christianity in
particular, demonstrating that there are no serious
incompatibilities between the Bible and scientific
theories such as evolution and the big bang,
debunking overblown accounts of wrongs perpetrated in
the name of religion such as the crusades, the inquisition,
the persecution of Galileo, witch hunts, and religious wars in
Europe, and arguing that the great mass murders of the
twentieth century can be laid at the feet not of religion, but
atheist regimes bent on building heaven on Earth. All this is
a pretty tall order, especially for a book of just 304 pages
of main text, but the author does a remarkably effective job
of it. While I doubt the arguments presented here will sway
those who have made a belligerent atheism central to their
self esteem, many readers may be surprised to discover that
the arguments of the atheists are nowhere near as one sided as
their propaganda would suggest.
Another main theme of the book is identifying how many
of the central components of Western civilisation:
limited government, religious toleration, individualism,
separation of church and state, respect for individual
human rights, and the scientific method, all have their
roots in the Judeo-Christian tradition, and how atheism
and materialism can corrode these pillars supporting the
culture which (rightly) allows the atheists the freedom
to attack it. The author is neither a fundamentalist
nor one who believes the Bible is true in a literal sense:
he argues that when the scriptures are read, as most
Christian scholars have understood them over two millennia,
as using a variety of literary techniques to convey
their message, there is no conflict between biblical
accounts and modern science and, in some cases, the
Bible seems to have anticipated recent discoveries.
D'Souza believes that Darwinian evolution is not in
conflict with the Bible and, while respectful of supporters
of intelligent design, sees no need to invoke it. He
zeroes in precisely on the key issue: that evolution cannot
explain the origin of life since evolution can only operate
on already living organisms upon which variation and selection
can occur.
A good deal of the book can be read as a defence of
religion in general against the arguments of atheism.
Only in the last two chapters does he specifically make the
case for the exceptionalism of Christianity. While
polemicists such as Dawkins and Hitchens come across as angry,
this book is written in a calm, self-confident tone and with
such a limpid clarity that it is a joy to read. As one who
has spent a good deal of time pondering the possibility that
we may be
living in a simulation created by an intelligent
designer (“it isn't a universe; it's a science fair
project”), this book surprised me as being 100%
compatible with that view and provided several additional
insights to expand my work in progress on the topic.
March 2008